Upper-Bounded Scalars and Argumentation-in-Language Theory

Scalar implicatures, such as the ‘not all’-implicature attached to “some”, have been at the center of debates on the semantics-pragmatics interface ever since Horn (1972). The question is whether ‘not all’ is part of the semantics of “some” or rather pragmatically inferred in context. The latter the...

Full description

Saved in:
Bibliographic Details
Main Author: Laura Devlesschouwer
Format: Article
Language:English
Published: Presses Universitaires du Midi 2019-12-01
Series:Anglophonia
Subjects:
Online Access:https://journals.openedition.org/anglophonia/2580
Tags: Add Tag
No Tags, Be the first to tag this record!
_version_ 1832579272384970752
author Laura Devlesschouwer
author_facet Laura Devlesschouwer
author_sort Laura Devlesschouwer
collection DOAJ
description Scalar implicatures, such as the ‘not all’-implicature attached to “some”, have been at the center of debates on the semantics-pragmatics interface ever since Horn (1972). The question is whether ‘not all’ is part of the semantics of “some” or rather pragmatically inferred in context. The latter theory, inspired by Grice’s (1975, 1989) work, is by far the more popular one. It analyzes scalars such as “some” as semantically lower-bounded, i.e. as meaning ‘at least some’. I will defend the view that “some” is both lower- and upper-bounded, i.e. on which “some” means ‘some, not all’. In order to do so, I will first propose a distinction between ‘upper bound’ and ‘scalar implicature’, following Ariel (2003, 2004, 2006, 2015). I will thereby defend the idea that scalars such as “some” are semantically upper-bounded, but not that scalar implicatures are semantic. Second, I will give an overview of the most cited arguments against ‘not all’-semantics for “some”: the entailment from “All…” to “Some…”, the non-redundancy of the expression “some, but not all”, the cancelability of scalar implicatures, and the non-paraphrasability of “some” as “some, but not all”. In the discussion of the non-redundancy argument, I will use Anscombre and Ducrot’s (1983) theory of ‘argumentation in language’, which has been largely ignored by pragmaticists working on scalar implicatures. This theory will also permit me to reanalyze some problematic examples presented by Ariel (2015) that have led her to conclude that scalar implicatures with “some” and “most” are rare.
format Article
id doaj-art-de028a3741bf487887c13d964fcfb9b6
institution Kabale University
issn 1278-3331
2427-0466
language English
publishDate 2019-12-01
publisher Presses Universitaires du Midi
record_format Article
series Anglophonia
spelling doaj-art-de028a3741bf487887c13d964fcfb9b62025-01-30T12:32:50ZengPresses Universitaires du MidiAnglophonia1278-33312427-04662019-12-012810.4000/anglophonia.2580Upper-Bounded Scalars and Argumentation-in-Language TheoryLaura DevlesschouwerScalar implicatures, such as the ‘not all’-implicature attached to “some”, have been at the center of debates on the semantics-pragmatics interface ever since Horn (1972). The question is whether ‘not all’ is part of the semantics of “some” or rather pragmatically inferred in context. The latter theory, inspired by Grice’s (1975, 1989) work, is by far the more popular one. It analyzes scalars such as “some” as semantically lower-bounded, i.e. as meaning ‘at least some’. I will defend the view that “some” is both lower- and upper-bounded, i.e. on which “some” means ‘some, not all’. In order to do so, I will first propose a distinction between ‘upper bound’ and ‘scalar implicature’, following Ariel (2003, 2004, 2006, 2015). I will thereby defend the idea that scalars such as “some” are semantically upper-bounded, but not that scalar implicatures are semantic. Second, I will give an overview of the most cited arguments against ‘not all’-semantics for “some”: the entailment from “All…” to “Some…”, the non-redundancy of the expression “some, but not all”, the cancelability of scalar implicatures, and the non-paraphrasability of “some” as “some, but not all”. In the discussion of the non-redundancy argument, I will use Anscombre and Ducrot’s (1983) theory of ‘argumentation in language’, which has been largely ignored by pragmaticists working on scalar implicatures. This theory will also permit me to reanalyze some problematic examples presented by Ariel (2015) that have led her to conclude that scalar implicatures with “some” and “most” are rare.https://journals.openedition.org/anglophonia/2580semantics-pragmatics interfaceargumentation in languagescalar implicaturescancelabilityargumentative scales
spellingShingle Laura Devlesschouwer
Upper-Bounded Scalars and Argumentation-in-Language Theory
Anglophonia
semantics-pragmatics interface
argumentation in language
scalar implicatures
cancelability
argumentative scales
title Upper-Bounded Scalars and Argumentation-in-Language Theory
title_full Upper-Bounded Scalars and Argumentation-in-Language Theory
title_fullStr Upper-Bounded Scalars and Argumentation-in-Language Theory
title_full_unstemmed Upper-Bounded Scalars and Argumentation-in-Language Theory
title_short Upper-Bounded Scalars and Argumentation-in-Language Theory
title_sort upper bounded scalars and argumentation in language theory
topic semantics-pragmatics interface
argumentation in language
scalar implicatures
cancelability
argumentative scales
url https://journals.openedition.org/anglophonia/2580
work_keys_str_mv AT lauradevlesschouwer upperboundedscalarsandargumentationinlanguagetheory